On
the Soul
1. Wherein is the
Criterion for the Apprehension of the Soul
All things that
exist are either known by sense or apprehended by thought. And what falls under
sense has its adequate demonstration in sense itself; for at once, with the
application, it creates in us the impression of what underlies it. But what is
apprehended by thought is known not by itself, but by its operations. The soul,
consequently, being unknown by itself, shall be known property by its effects.
2. Whether the
Soul Exists
Our body, when it
is put in action, is put in action either from without or from within. And that
it is not put in action from without, is manifest from the circumstance that it
is put in action neither by impulsion nor by traction, like soulless things.
And again, if it is put in action from within, it is not put in action according
to nature, like fire. For fire never loses its action as long as there is fire;
whereas the body, when it has become dead, is a body void of action. Hence, if
it is put in action neither from without, like soulless things, nor according
to nature, after the fashion of fire, it is evident that it is put in action by
the soul, which also furnishes life to it. If, then, the soul is shown to
furnish the life to our body, the soul will also be known for itself by its
operations.
3. Whether the
Soul is a Substance
That the soul is
a substance, is proved in the following manner. In the first place, because the
definition given to the term substance suits it very well. And that definition
is to the effect, that substance is that which, being ever identical, and ever
one in point of numeration with itself, is yet capable of taking on contraries
in succession. And that this soul, without passing the limit of its own proper
nature, takes on contraries in succession, is, I fancy, clear to everybody. For
righteousness and unrighteousness, courage and cowardice, temperance and
intemperance, are seen in it successively; and these are contraries. If, then,
it is the property of a substance to be capable of taking on contraries in
succession, and if the soul is shown to sustain the definition in these terms,
it follows that the soul is a substance. And in the second place, because if
the body is a substance, the soul must also be a substance. For it cannot be,
that what only has life imparted should be a substance, and that what imparts
the life should be no substance: unless one should assert that the non-existent
is the cause of the existent; or unless, again, one were insane enough to
allege that the dependent object is itself the cause of that very thing in
which it has its being, and without which it could not subsist.
4. Whether the
Soul is Incorporeal
That the soul is
in our body, has been shown above. We ought now, therefore, to ascertain in
what manner it is in the body. Now, if it is in juxtaposition with it, as one
pebble with another, it follows that the soul will be a body, and also that the
whole body will not be animated with soul, inasmuch as with a certain part it
will only be in juxtaposition. But if again, it is mingled or fused with the
body, the soul will become multiplex, and not simple, and will thus be
despoiled of the rationale proper to a soul. For what is multiplex is also
divisible and dissoluble; and what is dissoluble, on the other hand, is
compound; and what is compound is separable in a threefold manner. Moreover,
body attached to body makes weight; but the soul, subsisting in the body, does
not make weight, but rather imparts life. The soul, therefore, cannot be a
body, but is incorporeal.
Again, if the
soul is a body, it is put in action either from without or from within. But it
is not put in action from without; for it is moved neither by impulsion nor by
traction, like soulless things. Nor is it put in action from within, like
objects animated with soul; for it is absurd to talk of a soul of the soul: it
cannot, therefore, be a body, but it is incorporeal.
And besides, if
the soul is a body, it has sensible qualities, and is maintained by nurture.
But it is not thus nurtured. For if it is nurtured, it is not nurtured
corporeally, like the body, but incorporeally; for it is nurtured by reason. It
has not, therefore, sensible qualities: for neither is righteousness, nor
courage, nor any one of these things, something that is seen; yet these are the
qualities of the soul. It cannot, therefore, be a body, but is incorporeal.
Still further, as
all corporeal substance is divided into animate and inanimate, let those who
hold that the soul is a body tell us whether we are to call it animate or
inanimate.
Finally, if every
body has colour, and quantity, and figure, and if there is not one of these
qualities perceptible in the soul, it follows that the soul is not a body.
5. Whether the
Soul is Simple or Compound
We prove, then,
that the soul is simple, best of all, by those arguments by which its
incorporeality has been demonstrated. For if it is not a body, while every body
is compound, and what is composite is made up of parts, and is consequently
multiplex, the soul, on the other hand, being incorporeal, is simple; since
thus it is both uncompounded and indivisible into parts.
6. Whether Our
Soul is Immortal
It follows, in my
opinion, as a necessary consequence, that what is simple is immortal. And as to
how that follows, hear my explanation: Nothing that exists is its own
corrupter, else it could never have had any thorough consistency, even from the
beginning. For things that are subject to corruption are corrupted by
contraries: wherefore everything that is corrupted is subject to dissolution;
and what is subject to dissolution is compound; and what is compound is of many
parts; and what is made up of parts manifestly is made up of diverse parts; and
the diverse is not the identical: consequently the soul, being simple, and not
being made up of diverse parts, but being uncompound and indissoluble, must be,
in virtue of that, incorruptible and immortal.
Besides,
everything that is put in action by something else, and does not possess the
principle of life in itself, but gets it from that which puts it in action,
endures just so long as it is held by the power that operates in it; and
whenever the operative power ceases, that also comes to a stand which has its
capacity of action from it. But the soul, being self-acting, has no cessation
of its being. For it follows, that what is self-acting is ever-acting; and what
is ever-acting is unceasing; and what is unceasing is without end; and what is
without end is incorruptible; and what is incorruptible is immortal.
Consequently, if the soul is self-acting, as has been shown above, it follows
that it is incorruptible and immortal, in accordance with the mode of reasoning
already expressed.
And further,
everything that is not corrupted by the evil proper to itself, is
incorruptible; and the evil is opposed to the good, and is consequently its
corrupter. For the evil of the body is nothing else than suffering, and disease,
and death; just as, on the other hand, its excellency is beauty, life, health,
and vigour. If, therefore, the soul is not corrupted by the evil proper to
itself, and the evil of the soul is cowardice, intemperance, envy, and the
like, and all these things do not despoil it of its powers of life and action,
it follows that it is immortal.
7. Whether Our
Soul is Rational
That our soul is
rational, one might demonstrate by many arguments. And first of all from the
fact that it has discovered the arts that are for the service of our life. For
no one could say that these arts were introduced casually and accidentally, as
no one could prove them to be idle, and of no utility for our life. If, then,
these arts contribute to what is profitable for our life, and if the profitable
is commendable, and if the commendable is constituted by reason, and if these
things are the discovery of the soul, it follows that our soul is rational.
Again, that our
soul is rational, is also proved by the fact that our senses are not sufficient
for the apprehension of things. For we are not competent for the knowledge of
things by the simple application of the faculty of sensation. But as we do not
choose to rest in these without inquiry, that proves that the senses, apart from
reason, are felt to be incapable of discriminating between things which are
identical in form and similar in colour, though quite distinct in their
natures. If, therefore, the senses, apart from reason, give us a false
conception of things, we have to consider whether things that are can be
apprehended in reality or not. And if they can be apprehended, then the power
which enables us to get at them is one different from, and superior to, the
senses. And if they are not apprehended, it will not be possible for us at all
to apprehend things which are different in their appearance from the reality.
But that objects are apprehensible by us, is clear from the fact that we employ
each in a way adaptable to utility, and again turn them to what we please.
Consequently, if it has been shown that things which are can be apprehended by
us, and if the senses, apart from reason, are an erroneous test of objects, it
follows that the intellect is what distinguishes all things in reason, and
discerns things as they are in their actuality. But the intellect is just the
rational portion of the soul, and consequently the soul is rational.
Finally, because we do nothing without having first marked it out for ourselves; and as that is nothing else than just the high prerogative of the soul—for its knowledge of things does not come to it from without, but it rather sets out these things, as it were, with the adornment of its own thoughts, and thus first pictures forth the object in itself, and only thereafter carries it out to actual fact—and because the high prerogative of the soul is nothing else than the doing of all things with reason, in which respect it also differs from the senses, the soul has thereby been demonstrated to be rational.
Finally, because we do nothing without having first marked it out for ourselves; and as that is nothing else than just the high prerogative of the soul—for its knowledge of things does not come to it from without, but it rather sets out these things, as it were, with the adornment of its own thoughts, and thus first pictures forth the object in itself, and only thereafter carries it out to actual fact—and because the high prerogative of the soul is nothing else than the doing of all things with reason, in which respect it also differs from the senses, the soul has thereby been demonstrated to be rational.
by Saint Gregory Thaumaturgus
Photo taken from Wikimedia Commons
No comments:
Post a Comment
Thank you for your interest in our blog! Your comment will be viewed shortly to be added to our blog. :)